|
Research Flex ISBN: 978-93-93166-40-1 For verification of this chapter, please visit on http://www.socialresearchfoundation.com/books.php#8 |
Chomskyan Theory of Language: A Rationalist Combination of Formalist Methodology and Innatist Conclusions |
Dr. Suddhasattwa Banerjee
Assistant Professor
English
Hiralal Bhakat College,
Kolkata, West Bengal,
|
DOI: Chapter ID: 16064 |
This is an open-access book section/chapter distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution 4.0 International, which permits unrestricted use, distribution, and reproduction in any medium, provided the original author and source are credited. |
Abstract: In this paper I would
like to outline the basic philosophical and methodological assumptions behind
Chomsky's theory of Universal Grammar and the main objections to the theory
from within the Marxist tradition. My argument is that the biological determinist
framework of Chomsky's theory is an unsound philosophical and methodological
foundation for the scientific investigation of human affairs in general and
language in particular. There is an alternative in the tradition of materialist
investigation of language and mental phenomena associated with the name of
Vygotsky and others, which allows us to give full due to our material,
biological natures without at the same time preventing us from appreciating the
essentially socio-cultural determination of our activity and thinking.
One may usually have some powerful assumptions about the nature of humanity and
of human mental activity to be willing to accept the formalist methodology as
well as the innatist conclusions of Chomskyan linguistics. As we find, the
assumptions Chomsky makes, on which his whole research programme rests, are
biological determinist, which in philosophy means idealist. If we judge this
ideological framework to be untenable, then the viability of the linguistic
theory is called into question. And if we cannot find at once all the answers
to the structural puzzles Chomsky's theory purports to solve, we would do
better to be cautiously sceptical about the data than to be bounced into
embracing a set of assumptions which have devastating consequences for the
human sciences. Over the years,
Chomsky has employed a rather effective expository and rhetorical device which
consists in imagining how a super-intelligent extra-terrestrial being would go
about the study of human language and its grammatical structure. Chomsky's
Martian gets to the bottom of things very quickly, unencumbered by the
parochial earthbound attitudes, ideological distortions and downright stupidity
that humans are prone to. The superorganism attacks language - this
"curious biological phenomenon" - with natural scientific
methods ("the methods of rational inquiry"), quickly discovering
beneath the apparent chaos of surface forms, highly abstract principles of
syntactic organization, principles which are inviolable and yet have no
functional motivation in the exigencies of social communication. Accordingly,
the Martian attributes the human capacity for language to our biological
make-up, to the workings of an innate language faculty. This faculty contains a
"Universal Grammar”, a "mental organ" which provides a
grammatical blueprint for the "growth" of the grammars of particular
languages in interaction with the linguistic (and general social) surroundings.
Here we have, in a nutshell, the general framework of assumptions and the
methodology within which Chomskyan theoretical syntax, often referred to as
"autonomous syntax" has taken shape. Key Words Chomsky, Universal
Grammar, Biological Determinism, Formalism, Rationalism. Paper In this paper I would
like to outline the basic philosophical and methodological assumptions behind
Chomsky's theory of Universal Grammar and the main objections to the theory
from within the Marxist tradition. My argument is that the biological
determinist framework of Chomsky's theory is an unsound philosophical and
methodological foundation for the scientific investigation of human affairs in
general and language in particular. There is an alternative in the tradition of
materialist investigation of language and mental phenomena associated with the
name of Vygotsky and others, which allows us to give full due to our material,
biological natures without at the same time preventing us from appreciating the
essentially socio-cultural determination of our activity and thinking.
Onemay usuallyhave some powerful assumptions about the nature of humanity and
of human mental activity to be willing to accept the formalist methodology as
well as the innatist conclusions of Chomskyan linguistics. As we find, the
assumptions Chomsky makes, on which his whole research programme rests, are
biological determinist, which in philosophy means idealist. If we judge this
ideological framework to be untenable, then the viability of the linguistic
theory is called into question. And if we cannot find at once all the answers
to the structural puzzles Chomsky's theory purports to solve, we would do
better to be cautiously sceptical about the data than to be bounced into
embracing a set of assumptions which have devastating consequences for the
human sciences. Chomsky proposeda kind
of plausible theory of language. The different approaches he had between
E-language and I-language may be similar to the Brahe and other's observational
astronomy, which collected a vast body of data, and Ptolemy, Copernicus, and
Kepler's model of planetary motion, even though the details of the model might
be questionable. Chomsky's first generalization is also a legitimate step. But
his proposal of "innate ideas" has been resisted by some empiricists,
and he is characterized as rationalist. In our view, those empiricists make a
mistake. In order to clarify this issue we will cite Chomsky's statements in
spite of somewhat redundancy. Chomsky attempts to
develop his theory of linguistics as a discipline of natural sciences or
physical sciences, which are empirically based. He specifically objects to
'Abstract-linguistics' (Chomsky,1986) and he maintains that
the boundary between linguistics and natural sciences will shift or disappear.
The theory of mind aims to determine the properties of the initial
state ‘SO'and each attainable state ‘SL’ of the language
faculty, and the brain sciences seek to discover the mechanisms of the brain
that are the physical realizations of these states. (Chomsky,1986) Eventually,
the linguistics and the brain science will converge. Chomsky uses the term
'mechanism', which refers to the physical mechanism. (Chomsky,1986) He
says, one task of the brain sciences, is to discover the mechanisms of brain
that are the physical realization of the state SL.
What he means by physical realization is the physically encoded mental state on
the brain. "In contrast to E-language, the steady state of knowledge
(I-language) attained and the initial state So are real
elements of particular mind/brains, aspects of the ‘physical
world’, where we understand mental states and representations to be‘physically
encoded’ in some manner." (Chomsky,1986) Chomsky's
‘UG’ is ‘biologically determined’ (Chomsky,1986) principles
too. Chomsky seems to use 'physically' and 'biologically' interchangeable. In
this aspect Chomsky's universals that are biologically realized and physically
encoded in brain, are different from Descarte's ‘innate ideas’. Chomsky rejects the fictional and abstract objects and, especially, rejects the suggestion that knowledge of language should be taken to be an abstract "Platonic" entity. He says; "Knowing everything about the mind/brain, a Platonist would argue, we still have no basis for determining the truths of arithmetic or set theory, but there is not the slightest reason to suppose that there are truths of language that would still escape our grasp." (Chomsky,1986) He differentiates linguistics from mathematics and emphasizes the empirical aspect of linguistics and its relationship to brain sciences; therefore, the justification of his theory is not only a theoretical matter, but also an empirical that relies on the results of brain science. Based on Chomsky's positions on the nature of his linguistics theory, we conclude that he has been mistaken as a rationalist. In the next section, we will discuss some of the debates on this subjects and other related issues. The analogies Chomsky
draws between mental and physical organs and their growth have a definite
philosophical significance which he is keen to develop explicitly. Thus,
Chomsky contrasts the "deep and abstract" nature of the grammatical
knowledge acquired by the child with the "degenerate quality and narrowly
limited extent of the available data" on which the child bases his/her
grammar construction (Chomsky,1965). He notes the "striking
uniformity of the resulting grammars, and their independence of intelligence,
motivation, and emotional state" (Chomsky,1965), all of which
leaves little hope that much of the structure of the language can be learned by
an organism initially uninformed as to its general character" (Chomsky,1965).
It is this argument from the "poverty of the stimulus" (Chomsky,
1986), contrasting the knowledge acquired with its evidential base, which
is the central epistemological pillar of his biological determinist edifice.
This contrast is held to justify the postulation of highly specific and finely
tuned innate principles which "permit the organism to transcend
experience, reaching a high level of complexity that does not reflect the
limited and degenerate environment" (Chomsky, 1980). In more
traditional philosophical language, the argument has to do with the problem of
induction (sometimes referred to by Chomsky as "Plato's
problem", (Hacker, 1990). The same argument in relation to
children's learning of words is used to support a belief in the innateness of
all concepts. Chomsky's
philosophical stance has much to do with his approval of the refutation of
induction by the 18th century Scottish sceptical philosopher David Hume,
entailing the rejection of the empiricist principle that experience is the
source of human knowledge. Hume showed that the framing of general scientific
laws cannot be justified logically, rationally from experience alone, which led
him to "the disastrous conclusion that from experience and observation
nothing is to be learnt" (Russell, 1991) and from there
to a denial of the possibility of rational belief ‘tout court’. The
logical outcome, in fact, was solipsism. Chomsky, however, sees a solution to
the Humean problem in a version of the doctrine of innate ideas: if knowledge
cannot derive from experience then it must belong to the mind itself; what we
call "knowledge" is produced in-house, so to speak, caused by the
internal structure and working of the mind - the physical constitution of the
brain itself determines what is and what is not thinkable and knowable. Here
the influence of the Cartesian and Kantian traditions makes itself felt
although the logic of Chomsky's position forces him to sharply distance himself
from the Cartesian picture of the mind as a "universal
instrument" (Chomsky,1988), able to know anything and
everything, since, if it is the structure of the brain itself which determines
the content and possibilities of human knowledge, there must necessarily be
"sharp limits on attainable knowledge" (Chomsky,1979). And so to the main
epistemological conundrum at the heart of the Chomskyan doctrine: if knowledge
is some kind of physical substance grown in the brain, what, then, of truth? In
Chomskyan parlance, what of "the relation between the class of humanly
accessible theories and the class of true theories" (Chomsky,1980) On
Chomsky's premisses, truth can only arise via a coincidence or intersection of
mental (ie brain) properties with properties of reality: "Where such an
intersection exists, a human being can attain real knowledge. And, conversely,
he cannot attain real knowledge beyond that intersection" (Chomsky, 1979).
However, Chomsky has already argued that "we're not going to find that one
system has the same structural properties as other systems" (Edgley et
al, 1989) from which it follows that "there is no particular
biological reason why such an intersection should exist" (Chomsky,
1979). He is forced to conclude that there "is no particular
reason to suppose that the science-forming capacities of humans or their
mathematical abilities permit them to conceive of theories approximating the
truth in every (or any) domain, or to gain insight into the laws of
nature" (Chomsky:1980). In other words, there is no reason
for believing that any "knowledge" we have is true knowledge, and
good reasons for believing that none of it is - a radical scepticism foreign to
Descartes but acceptable to Kant who believed that the world of real things
outside the mind ("Things-in-themselves") was in principle
unknowable. But now the twist.
Instead of denying, with Kant, the possibility of real knowledge of things,
Chomsky gives the epistemological screw an extra turn, professing a Cartesian
faith in the power of human knowledge. For Descartes, the worlds of thought and
matter, despite having diametrically opposed properties, nevertheless
corresponded exactly, because God made them coincide. Chomksy, too, believes
that true knowledge exists, with physics being the prime example (Chomsky, 1979).
But God, apparently, is not responsible; it is, instead, "just blind luck
if the human science-forming capacity, a particular component of the human
biological endowment, happens to yield a result that conforms more or less to
the truth about the world" (Chomsky,1988). Physics, then,
may indeed be such an instance of a "lucky accident" (Chomsky, 1979),
of "a remarkable historical accident resulting from chance convergence of
biological properties of the human mind with some aspect of the real
world" (Chomsky, 1979). Truth depends, then, on a "kind of
biological miracle" (Chomsky, 1979). Chomsky's linguistic
theory is based on the following empirical facts: "child learns language
with limited stimuli", or the problem of poverty of evidence. (Chomsky,
1986) The input during the period of a natural language acquisition is
circumscribed and degenerate. The output simply cannot be accounted for by the
learning mechanism only, such as induction and analogy on the input. The output
and input differ both in quantity and quality. A subject knows linguistic facts
without instruction or even direct evidence. These empirical facts,
"knowledge without ground", (Chomsky, 1968) are
expressed: "Knowledge of language is normally attained through brief
exposure, and the character of the acquired knowledge may be largely
predetermined." (Chomsky, 1969) This predetermined
knowledge is some "notion of structure", in the mind of the speaker ,
which guides the subject in acquiring a natural language of his own. For a
subject to know a natural language is for him to have a certain I-language.
Language acquiring, in terms of I-language, corresponds to the change of a
subject's mind/brain state. To know the language L is for the
subject's (H's) mind/brain, initially to be in a state So,
to be set to a certain state ‘SL’. (Chomsky, 1986) One
task of the brain sciences will be to explain what it is about H's
brain (in particular, its language faculty) that corresponds to H's
knowing L. He makes an
important hypothesis that universal grammar (UG). UG is a
characterization of these innate principle of language faculty,
I-language. (Chomsky, 1986) He then postulates some detailed
structure of UG. It is a system of conditions on grammars, constraints on the
form and interpretation of grammar at all levels, from the deep structures of
syntax, through the transformational component, to the rules that interpret
syntactic structures semantically and phonetically. The study of linguistic
universals, which is classified as formal or substantive, is the study of the
properties of UG for a natural language. (6) Substantive universals
concern the vocabulary for the description of language and a formal linguistic
universal involve the character of the rules that appear in grammars and the
ways in which they can be interconnected. Language-acquisition device uses
primary linguistic data as the empirical basis for language learning to meet
explanatory adequacy that is defined in UG, and to select one of the potential
grammars, which is permitted by UG. Chomsky then makes two
explicit hypothesis, ‘pure’ speech community and a ‘common’ grammar. A
‘pure’speech community excludes contradictory choices for certain of options
permitted by ‘UG’ and the property of mind described by ‘UG’ is a species
characteristic, common to all humans. The second hypothesis
implies that the study of one language, such as English, may provide crucial
evidence concerning the structure of some other language. Acquisition of
language then, is a matter of adding to one's store of UG rules, or modifying
this system, as new data are processed. (Chomsky, 1970) The nature of
knowledge of language, which is closely tied to human knowledge in general,
makes it a logical step for Chomsky to generalize his theory. The linguistic
theory for special 'Plato problem' can be applied to 'Plato's problem' to
knowledge in general, providing that an empirical evidence of such problem for
a certain knowledge. He says, his innate principle includes syntax, phonology,
and morphology, and semantics. By 'semantics' he means the study of the
relation between language and the world — in particular, the study of truth and
reference. (Chomsky, 1986) At the same time, he also
generalizes his idea of ‘UG’, especially the process of parameter determination
in acquiring a particular natural language for a subject. "This result of
this process of parameter determination and periphery formation is a full and
richly articulated system of knowledge. ...The same may well be true of large
areas of what might be called 'common-sense knowledge and
understanding'". (Chomsky, 1986) The first
generalization, generalization of 'Plato's problem' to knowledge in general, is
correct. The second generalization, seems to us, is too hasty. The advances in
neural science and mathematics have produced new theory on complex systems. For
a vast complicated system as human brain, which is tremendously flexible and
which processes abstract concepts at many different levels, the theory of
parameter determination over-simplifies the problem we are facing. Chomsky tries to
differentiate himself from the linguistic behaviourism and he emphasizes some
of reasonable core of "rationalism" to make a statement that my
"sausage-making machines" (Danto, 1969) is not tabula
rasa, but has complex, dedicated parts and structure. He somewhat
identifies himself with the tradition of the rationalist philosophy of language
and with philosophical grammar. (Chomsky, 1970) He is not
satisfied with the explanatory power of the descriptive grammar. Philosophical
grammar is "typically concerned with data not for itself but as evidence
for deeper, hidden organizing principles,..." (Chomsky, 1970)However,
it may be surprising, his term 'rationalism' is equivalent to 'natural
science', He states that the issue of rationalist philosophy of language
"is not between descriptive and prescriptive grammar, but between
description and explanation, between grammar as 'natural history' and grammar
as a kind of 'natural philosophy' or, in modern terms, 'natural
science.'" (Chomsky, 1986) He particularly criticizes the
lack of physical, empirical aspects of Cartesian rationalism. (Chomsky,
1986) Rationalism stressed
the power of reason as opposed to empirical facts and used deductive reasoning
as the basis for their knowledge system. Chomsky's theory is an empirical
science and his method is largely based on linguistic empirical data.
Therefore, Chomsky's theory is not rationalist in the classical sense. Some of
his opponents (Quine, Wells) confuse what Chomsky is claiming and what he is
doing. (Goodman, 1969) Understanding of
Chomsky's position on those issues, some of the objections to his theory become
automatically invalid, Goodman (Goodman, 1969)raises a question.
How does Chomsky start from some subtle difference in linguistics and then
moves on to innate ideas? "I know what a horse with spirit is, but not
what the spirit is without the horse." (Goodman, 1969) This
UG is not something that "a spirit without a horse" at all. On the other hand,
Chomsky's theory is empirical, but different from behaviorism linguistics. On
the issue of "innate structure", Harman does not accept Chomsky's
theory of innate structures. He said: "I view linguistics, it is closer to
both anthropology and the behavioural sciences than he would apparently
allow." (Harman,1969) Quine argues: "This
indisputable point about language is in no conflict with latter-day attitudes
that are associated with the name of empiricism, or behaviourism. (Chomsky,
1986) There are two major differences between behaviourism and
Chomsky's theory. Behaviourism treats a complex system as a black box, a
functional mechanism. If two black box function exact the same, behaviourism
and functionalism regards them exact the same. This is Quine's so-called
'enigma doctrine'. He says, "English speakers obey, in this sense, any and
all of the extensionally equivalent systems of grammar that demarcate the right
totality of well-formed English sentences." (Quine, 1972) However,
Chomsky's "theories of grammar and UG are empirical theories" and his
systems of grammar is physically encoded in some manner. The development of
brain science will discover the very physical structure of human brain, and
there can be only one of a set of "extensionally equivalent systems of
grammar" is correctly attributed to the speaker-hearer as a property that
is the same as that is physically encoded, where some other one merely happens
to fit the speaker's behaviour but does not correctly represent the physical
facts. The second difference is reflected by the relationship between
I-language and E-language. E-language, as the traditional behaviourist
linguistics, deals with steady-state language, or mature language; while
I-language in Chomsky's theory specifies not only the internal characteristics
of language, but also deals with a dynamic process, language acquiring process,
from initial state So to the steady state ‘SL’. (Nagel,
1969) E-language is independent of a individual's history, while
I-language explains the language aspect of individual's history. This dynamic
process puts more constraints on the characteristics of the languages.
I-languages may reach the same steady state ‘SL’ and realize the steady
state languages that have "extensionally equivalent systems of
grammar"; while these I-languages may specify different dynamic processes
that reach ‘SL’. These processes differentiate I-languages one another and
some of them can be proved to be wrong theories regarding the language
acquisition process. Therefore, extensionally equivalent systems of grammar in
the traditional grammar sense is not necessarily equivalent in terms of
I-language. Nagel questioned
whether the initial contribution of the organism to language-learning is
properly described as knowledge. (Nagel, 1869) Dummett
questions the concept of unconscious knowledge. (Chomsky, 1986) He
holds that there is an extremely important innate capacity but it would not be
called innate knowledge in either case. Chomsky introduces "cognize"
in trying to resolve the issue. It can easily be understood through an analogy.
In computer science, a computation can be either realized through software,
which is written in computer language, or through hardware, which is built by
the logic circuits composed of physical parts. Both functions exactly the same.
If we can do an extrapolation or analogy, ideas might be realized through
abstract symbol systems or through neural-network. The two mode of structures may
have effects on the recognisability. This is a speculation. But our point is
that ‘UG’ is proposed as hypothesis, and if the 'notion of structure' is
correct, other hypothesis may be assumed on what kind of structure is and how
the structure operates. The final settlement relies on new development of brain
sciences. ‘UG’ as a hypothesis
raises questions about to what extend the hypothesis correctly captures the
structure of brain. Danto says: "...to what
extent does the innate structure of language formation sink into the world,
giving it linguistic form, or the form of our language. So far as LA is
universal, we live perforce in the same world if the structure of our world
reflects the structure of language. Obviously, something produced by means of a
different LA would not be recognizably a language, nor would the world
correlative with this, if there is this correlatively, be recognizably the
world. A wholly different language or a wholly different world would be
unintelligible, but is the very idea unintelligible?". (Danto,
1969) Chomsky treats the
innate idea as a fixed form (common grammar hypothesis), which resembles
rationalist doctrine of ideas; while his attempts in providing a natural
science of language is not consistent with such hypothesis. In this aspect,
Herbert Spencer (Principle of Psychology) might be right that innate
ideas, such as adopt form of thought, like the perception of space and time, or
the notions of quantity and cause, which Kant supposed innate, are merely
instinctive ways of thinking; and as instincts are habits acquired by the race
but native to the individual, so these categories are mental habits slowly
acquired in the course of evolution, and now part of our intellectual heritage.
In Spencer's word, "the inheritance of accumulating modifications".
If this is correct, chimpanzee and human ability in communication and maybe
language can be bridged in principle, and the study of chimpanzee's brain would
help to discover the innate structure physically encoded in a certain manner
too. Over the years,
Chomsky has employed a rather effective expository and rhetorical device which
consists in imagining how a super-intelligent extra-terrestrial being would go
about the study of human language and its grammatical structure. Chomsky's
Martian gets to the bottom of things very quickly, unencumbered by the
parochial earthbound attitudes, ideological distortions and downright stupidity
that humans are prone to. The superorganism attacks language - this
"curious biological phenomenon" (Chomsky,1988) - with natural
scientific methods ("the methods of rational inquiry")(Chomsky,1988),
quickly discovering beneath the apparent chaos of surface forms, highly
abstract principles of syntactic organization, principles which are inviolable
and yet have no functional motivation in the exigencies of social
communication. Accordingly, the Martian attributes the human capacity for
language to our biological make-up, to the workings of an innate language
faculty. This faculty contains a "Universal Grammar, a "mental
organ" which provides a grammatical blueprint for the "growth"
of the grammars of particular languages in interaction with the linguistic (and
general social) surroundings. Here we have, in a nutshell, the general framework
of assumptions and the methodology within which Chomskyan theoretical syntax,
often referred to as "autonomous syntax" (Newmeyer, 1986) has
taken shape. Facts aside, this is,
on first encounter, a persuasive and plausible picture of the nature of
language and its structure. It appears to have the merit, not least, of
reconciling the study of language with already established and respectable
sciences, thereby helping to promote a thorough-going scientific and
philosophical realism, a materialistic monism (or "scientific monism",
(Salkie, 1990). On the other hand, one may have doubts. Of course, one
can hardly object to rational methods of enquiry, or to the demand for the same
standards of rationality in linguistics as in the "hard" sciences.
And yet, to assume in advance that linguistic facts are biological facts is
hardly in keeping with the finest standards of terrestrial thought, something
that might lead us to temper our enthusiasm for contact with other worlds. Why
does our Martian superorganism not entertain the possibility that language is,
say, a cultural form? I will return to the argument below.(Chomsky, 1986) Chomsky's rational
methods entail drastic consequences for the human sciences as a whole, for
every sphere of human mental activity, subjected to such enquiry, turns out to
require a mental organ of its own. To each domain Chomsky allots a dedicated
biological substratum allowing species- specific mental activity to flourish
over a certain highly restricted field "accessible" to the innate
faculty while denying access to areas which "lie beyond the reach of our
minds, structured and organised as they are" (Chomsky,1979).
Syntax is the province of one such organ, word meaning is another, to the
surprise, perhaps, of those who think that Chomsky's innatism is restricted to
the form of language - as if form and content could so easily be dissociated.
Thus, Chomsky believes that the speed and precision with which children pick up
new words "leaves no real alternative to the conclusion that the child
somehow has the concepts available before experience with language and is
basically learning labels for concepts that are already part of his or her
conceptual apparatus" (Chomsky,1988). The same applies, he
claims, "even for the technical concepts of the natural sciences" (Chomsky ,1988).
The very method of scientific thought is also fixed a ‘priori’ in
a "science-forming capacity" (Chomsky,1980) which
permits, again, only "accessible" theories, i.e. those which conform
to biologically determined specifications. As regards activity in the literary
or musical spheres, Chomsky is similarly convinced that "a certain range
of possibilities has been explored to create structures of marvellous
intricacy, while others are never considered or if explored, lead to the
production of work that does not conform to normal human capacities" (Chomsky:1988).
He also believes that "the moral and ethical system acquired by the child
owes much to some innate human faculty" (Chomsky:1988). The outcome of this
grandiose reductionism is the marginalisation of the effective domain of the
historical, the social and the cultural in human affairs. Indeed, the very
concept of "society" as a coherent systemic organism becomes
problematic, and in fact Chomsky makes no secret of his scepticism about the
possibility of a genuine social science (Chomsky, 1979). On
occasion, Chomsky has considered extending his innatist approach to the sphere
of social interaction itself, speculating that we might have "a sort of
'universal grammar' of possible forms of social interaction, and it is this
system which helps us to organize intuitively our imperfect perceptions of
social reality" while adding that "it does not follow necessarily
that we are capable of developing conscious theories in this domain through the
exercise of our 'science-forming faculties'" (Chomsky, 1979). References 1. Bakhurst, D., 'Social Memory
in Soviet Thought', D Middleton D., Edwards D. (Eds.) Collective
Remembering, London: Sage Publications. 1990.Print. 2. Bakhurst, D., Consciousness
and Revolution in Soviet Philosophy: From the Bolsheviks to Evald llyenkov,
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. 1991.Print. 3. Chomsky, N., Aspects
of the Theory of Syntax, Cambridge, Mass: MIT Press. 1965. Print. 4. Chomsky, N Language
and Mind, New York: Harcourt, Brace, Jovanovich. 1972. Print. 5. Chomsky, N., Reflections
on Language, London: Temple Smith. 1976. Print. 6. Chomksy, N.,Language
and Responsibility, Hassocks: Harvester Press. 1979. Print. 7. Chomsky, N., Rules
and Representations, Oxford: Basil Blackwell. 1980. Print. 8. Chomsky, N.,Knowledge
of Language: Its Nature, Origin and Use, New York: Prager. 1986. Print. 9. Chomsky, N.,On Power
and Ideology, Boston: South End Press. Print. 1987. 10. Chomsky, N.,Language
and Problems of Knowledge, Cambridge, Mass: MIT Press. Print. 1988. 11. Chomsky, N., Necessary
Illusions, London: Pluto Press. 1989. Print. 12. Danto,
"Semantical Vehicles, Understanding, and Innate Ideas", Language
and Philosophy, New York University Press, 1969. Print.
P.P.122-137. 13. Desmond,
A., Moore, J., Darwin, London: Michael Joseph. 1991. Print. 14. Engels, F., Dialectics
of Nature, London: Lawrence and Wishart. 1941. Print. P.P.37-42. 15. Goldman,
A.I., "Innate Knowledge", Innate Ideas, California: University
California Press, 1966. Print. 16. Goodman,
N., "The Emperor's New Ideas", Language and Philosophy, New
York University Press, 1969, Print. P.P.138-142. 17. Gregory,
R. L. (Ed.) The Oxford Companion to the Mind, Oxford: Oxford
University Press. 1987. Print. 18. Harman,
"Linguistic Competence and Empiricism," Language and
Philosophy, New York: New York University Press, 1969.
Print. P.P.143-151. 19. Harris, R., The
Language Makers, Ithaca: Cornell University Press. 1980. Print. 20. Ilvenkov, E.V., Dialectical
Logic, Moscow: Progress. 1977. Print. 21. Ilyenkov E. V., 'The
Concept of the Ideal', Philosophy in the USSR: Problems of Dialectical
Materialism, Moscow: Progress. 1977. Print. 22. Ilyenkov, E. V., The
Dialectics of the Abstract and the Concrete in Marx's 'Capital', Moscow:
Progress 1982. Print. 23. Jones, P. E., Marxism,
Materialism, and Language Structure, Part One: General Principles,
Sheffield: Pavic Publications. 1991. Print. 24. Keat, R., Urry,
J., Social Theory as Science, London: Routledge. 1975. Print. 25. Leontiev, A. N.,
'Activity and Consciousness', Philosophy in the USSR: Problems of
Dialectical Materialism, Moscow: Progress. 1977. Print. 26. Leontiev, A. N., Activity,
Consciousness, and Personality, Englewood Cliffs, New Jersey: Prentice-Hall
Inc. 1978. Print. 27. Leontiev, A. N., Problems
in the Development of the Mind, Moscow: Progress. 1981. Print. 28. Luria, A. R., The
Working Brain, New York: Basic Books. 1973. Print. 29. Luria, A. R.Basic
Problems of Neurolinguistics, Mouton: The Hague.1976. Print. 30. Luria, A. R., Language
and Cognition, New York: Wiley & Sons. 1981. Print. 31. Marx, K.,
"Theses on Feuerbach",Marx K. and Engels F., Selected Works,
Vol 1, Moscow: Progress. 1969. Print. P.P. 13-15 32. Mikhailov,
F. T.,The Riddle of the Self, Moscow: Progress. 1980. Print. 33. Moore,
T., Carling, C., Understanding Language: Towards a Post-Chomskyan
Linguistics, London: Macmillan. 1982. Print. 34. Nagel,
T., "Linguistics and Epistemology", Language and
Philosophy, Mew York: New York University Press, 1969, Print.
P.P.171-181. 35. Newmeyer,
F. J., The Politics of Linguistics, Chicago: University of Chicago
Press. 1986. Print. 36. Nicholls.
J., (Ed.) Language and Learning: An Interactional Perspective,
London: The Falmer Press. 1986.Print. 37. Pateman,
T.,Language in Mind and Language in Society, Oxford: Clarendon Press.
1987. Print. 38. Plekhanov,
G., "The Development of the Monist View of History", Selected
Philosophical Works, Vol 1, London: Lawrence & Wishart. 1961.
Print.P.P.542-782. 39. Quine,
W.V.O., "Linguistics and Philosophy", Language and
Philosophy, New York University Press, 1969, Print.
P.P.95-98. 40. Quine,
W.V.O., "Methodological Reflections on Current Linguistic
Theory," Semantics of Natural Language, Humanities Press,
1972. Print. 41. Radford,
A., Transformational Syntax: A student's guide to Chomsky's Extended
Standard Theory, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. 1981. Print. 42. Rose, S.
(Ed.), Against Biological Determinism, London: Allison and Busby.
1982. Print. 43. Rose, S.,
Lewontin, S. C., & Kamin, L. J.,Not in our Genes: Biology, Ideology and
Human Nature, London: Penguin. 1990.Print. 44. Russell,
B., History of Western Philosophy, London: Routledge [Second
Edition]. 1991.Print. 45. Salkie,
R., The Chomsky Update: Linguistics and Politics, London: Unwin
Hyman. 1990.Print. 46. Sampson,
G., The Form of Language, London: Weidenfeld. 1975. Print. 47. Vygotsky,
L.S.,Thought and Language, Cambridge, Mass: MIT Press. 1962.Print. 48. Vygotsky,
L.S., Mind in Society, Cambridge, Mass: Harvard University Press.
1978.Print. 49. Wells,
G., 'Language and Learning: An Interactional Perspective', Wells G., Wertsch, J
V (Eds.) The Concept of Activity in Soviet Psychology, New York: ME
Sharpe. 1985.Print. 50. Wertsch,
J. V., Vygotsky and the Social Formation of Mind, Cambridge Mass: Harvard
University Press. 1985.Print. 51. Wertsch, J. V., (Ed.) Culture, Communication and Cognition: Vygotskian Perspectives, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. 1985. Print. |